Libertatem Magazine

H.L.A.Hart: Life and Works

Contents of this Page

Introduction 

Herbert Lionel Adolphus Hart (HLA Hart) was born on 18th July 1907 in England and was a child of Simeon and Rose Samson Hart. Hart graduated from New College, Oxford, and then practised as a barrister from 1929 onwards in Chancery courts of London. During World War II, Hart was called upon by the British War Department to serve in Military Intelligence. So, from 1939 to 1945, Hart worked as a civil servant at the British Intelligence Division during which he got married to Jennifer Fischer Williams and had one daughter and three sons. Hart also fulfilled the requirements for an advanced degree and was awarded an M.A. from Oxford in 1942.

According to Neil McCormick in the book H.L.A.Hart- ‘After sixteen years of intensely practical work in the law and then in war service he returned to the academic life. His aims had nothing to do with applying philosophy to legal problems. But, as it turned out, his legal experience in the Chancery … was particularly relevant to the current concerns of his fellow philosophers, for whom the study of the uses of language in practical as well as theoretical ways had assumed a new urgency.‘ Thus Hart came to the field of jurisprudence almost by accident.

Hart succeeded A.L. Goodhart’s position as Chair of Jurisprudence at Oxford and served as a Professor of Jurisprudence from 1952 to 1968. During which he was also a visiting professor at Harvard University(1956-1957) and the University of California at Los Angeles(196-62). In 1968, Hart resigned as the Chair of Jurisprudence and became the Principal of Brasenose College, Oxford(1972-1978).

Advanced legal positivism 

Hart drew heavily on the works of Jeremy Bentham and John Austin as a part of traditional legal positivism. Legal positivists are based on three tenets:

  1. What the law is
  2. Analysis of legal concepts
  3. Laws are commands issued by a sovereign

Hart agreed on the first two tenets but refused to accept the third tenet. He argued that laws are not obeyed because of the coercive demands of the government but from the social rules.

The concept of law 

In The Philosophy of Law: An Introduction to Jurisprudence, Jeffrie G. Murphy and Jules L. Coleman allude to Hart’s The Concept of Law (1961), as being “all around viewed as the main commitment to the lawful way of thinking of [the 20th] century. Hart gives the hypothesis of legitimate positivism the most deliberate and amazing assertion it has at any point gotten and is at any point prone to get.” In The Concept of Law, Hart contended that Austin established a framework for a magnificent hypothesis of law by outlining among laws and ethics, however, failed to review law as a weapon of an enormous harasser who requests consistency forcibly.

Hart contended that an overall set of laws is not an arrangement of individual laws, but instead is an association of essential and auxiliary principles. Essential standards force a commitment: what a resident can or cannot do. Auxiliary laws characterize points of interest of the essential standards. To represent his hypothesis, Hart requested that his pursuers envision a pre-legitimate society, that is, one that needed laws, and afterwards envision the sorts of issues that may torment such a general public. To make changes to dispose of these pathologies is to make laws. The general set of laws is at that point, basically characterized, those progressions endorsed by the general public to fix social issues.

Hart noticed that even a pre-lawful society would follow accepted practices. Regardless of whether there was no particular law against it, strolling around stripped in many social orders would be considered outside the scope of worthy social conduct. Hart called these essential principles: rules coordinated to all people in a given society that force commitments. In contrast to Austin, who proposed that such principles are continued to keep away from discipline, Hart contended that an essential guideline forces commitment since it sets a norm for analysis or avocation inside the general public.

The general public who conformed to essential guidelines alone, Hart recognized, would experience the ill effects of troubles. To begin with, the vulnerability would emerge concerning what the standards are, the way controls are applied, and what to do if rules struggle. Second, essential guidelines are static and do not change as the social, monetary, and world of politics changes. Third, essential principles alone are wasteful because there is no efficiently recommended response for when there is struggle preposterous or the standards are broken. In light of these evident troubles, Hart proposed the expansion of auxiliary standards, or rules about rules, as he noted in The Concept of Law: “They indicate the manners by which the essential guidelines might be definitively learned, presented, dispensed with, fluctuated, and the reality of their infringement convincingly decided.” According to Hart, three fundamental optional principles exist rules of acknowledgement, rules of progress, and rules of settling. They are laws that build up the definitive design by which essential laws are characterized and authorized.

Hart kept up that a general set of laws should be drawn closer from an inner perspective. As a member inside the framework, an eyewitness brings an expectation that the law should have complied. In The Legal Philosophy of H.L.A. Hart, Michael Martin examines Hart’s hypothesis of disguise: “Social entertainers can unexpectedly see their conduct: they can acknowledge the standards of a framework and use them to direct their activities and to assess the activities of others or they can observe the guidelines without tolerating them. Hart keeps up that to have an overall set of laws, at any rate, the authorities of the framework should take the inside perspective: they should acknowledge the principles of the framework and assess others’ activities as far as them.”

The Concept of Law turned into the measuring stick by which both Hart’s allies and doubters were estimated. As McCormick noted, “It is a work of worldwide greatness which even its most grounded pundits have recognized as a magnum opus worth the commendation of cautious nullification.”

Other works 

The Concept of Law was not Hart’s only significant book. Hart altered three books on Bentham: Jeremy Bentham, Of Laws in General (1970), Bentham, An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation (1970), and Bentham, Comment on the Commentaries [and] A Fragment on Government (1977). Hart distributed two additional works after his retirement: Essays on Bentham: Studies in Jurisprudence and Political Theory (1982) and Essays on Jurisprudence and Philosophy (1983). Throughout his recognized vocation, Hart composed various distributed papers. The most powerful was “Definition and Theory in Jurisprudence” (debut address, Oxford, 1953), “Are There Any Natural Rights?” (1967), and “Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals” (1958).


Libertatem.in is now on Telegram. Follow us for regular legal updates and judgments from the Court. Follow us on Google NewsInstagramLinkedInFacebook & Twitter. You can also subscribe to our Weekly Email Updates. You can also contribute stories like this and help us spread awareness for a better society. Submit Your Post Now.

About the Author